1058 lines
50 KiB
Markdown
1058 lines
50 KiB
Markdown
# Analysis
|
||
|
||
## Accounts from the Philosophy of Science
|
||
|
||
(Towards another chapter. What l want to do is: ,
|
||
|
||
1. present the DN account, and it's defenders.
|
||
2. present the conventional response
|
||
3. present the radical response
|
||
4. add some notes of my own, if possible supported by sources, on the
|
||
polemic nature of explanation)
|
||
|
||
This section looks at accounts of explanation culled from the Philosophy
|
||
of Science. My reason for starting with this field of study is that
|
||
philosophers in this field have a commitment to express their ideas in
|
||
strictly formal ways.
|
||
|
||
Furthermore, the matter of explanation has always been central to the
|
||
study \[see e.g. van Fraassen 80, p 92; Nagel 61, p 4\]. Thus it might
|
||
be hoped that they would produce a formal account of what constitutes a
|
||
good argument. While it is not necessarily the case that what can be
|
||
expressed formally will be computationally tractable, a formal statement
|
||
of an idea is at least a good start towards computability.
|
||
|
||
In fact this link between formal statement and computability is what
|
||
makes the methodology of Artificial Intelligence such a good tool for
|
||
the philosopher. Where a formal description can be encoded into a
|
||
computer language in a computationally tractable manner, the computer
|
||
programme can be used to evaluate how well the description matches the
|
||
phenomenon described, simply by observing how well the computer models
|
||
this phenomenon. I shall pursue this argument in the second half of this thesis.
|
||
|
||
### Some definitions
|
||
|
||
In part of the discussion that follows, it will be necessary to use a
|
||
shorthand to describe some of the different positions that have been
|
||
adopted at one time or A another by philosophers of science. Two
|
||
important positions are realism and A empiricism. The positions are only
|
||
peripheral to the discussion that follows, but in using them I will
|
||
generally follow van Fraassen's usage: by realism, I will mean the view
|
||
that “...science aims to find a true description of unobservable
|
||
processes that explain the observable ones...” \[van Fraassen '8O page
|
||
3\] This view holds that a theory is only adequate if it's description
|
||
of the world is correct in the finest detail.
|
||
|
||
By contrast, by empiricism I shall mean the view that a theory is
|
||
adequate provided it gives a correct account of the observable
|
||
phenomena. Any underlying mechanism may be postulated, provided that it
|
||
accounts for the observable behaviour.
|
||
|
||
I shall also use another term from the same debate - positivism. I shall
|
||
not use this in the precise sense that van Frassen gives it, but in a
|
||
looser, more colloquial sense, to define that group of doctrines
|
||
(including all realist and most empiricist doctrines) which hold that
|
||
there is a real world, and that that real world is accurately reflected
|
||
in our perceptions.
|
||
|
||
### Aristotle to Nagel
|
||
|
||
The Philosophy of Science has had the development of an account of
|
||
explanation as one of its central projects since Aristotle. Aristotle's
|
||
account of explanation was broadly that an explanation was an argument
|
||
which had the explicandum as its consequent. As, to Aristotle, arguments
|
||
should be constructed as syllogisms or chains of syllogisms, the correct
|
||
explanation in response to 'How do you know that Socrates is mortal?'
|
||
would be:
|
||
|
||
Socrates is a man;
|
||
All men are mortal;
|
||
Therefore Socrates is mortal.
|
||
|
||
*a syllogism of the mood barbara*
|
||
|
||
This account, which has become known as the 'hypothetico-deductive' or
|
||
'deductive-nomological' account of explanation, has effectively been the
|
||
dominant account ever since. The classic statement of this account in
|
||
the present century is probably that given by Hempel \[Hempel, 65\].
|
||
Ernest Nagel \[Nagel, 61\] attempted to go beyond this to a more general
|
||
account of explanation, but he included the deductive-nomological form
|
||
as the first of the four types of explanation which he describes.
|
||
|
||
Nagel claims, rather baldly, that “Explanations are answers to the
|
||
question 'Why?'”, but later goes on to note "...the important point that
|
||
even answers to the limited class of questions introduced by 'Why' are
|
||
not all of the same kind." His four types of explanation are: deductive
|
||
explanations, probabilistic explanations, functional or teleological
|
||
explanations, and genetic explanations.
|
||
|
||
#### Deductive explanations
|
||
|
||
Nagel's deductive explanations have the formal structure of a deductive
|
||
argument, rather in the manner of a logical proof. This is essentially
|
||
the deductive nomological explanation. In the case of the explanation of
|
||
singularities, it fits neatly with the Toulmin \[below\] - or indeed the
|
||
sylogistic - form of argument: data, plus principle, imply conclusion:
|
||
|
||
> "It is evident that at least one of the premises in a deductive explanation of a singular explicandum must be a universal law..." (page 31)
|
||
|
||
> "... a deductive scientific explanation, whose explicandum is the
|
||
> occurance of some event or the possession of some property by a given
|
||
> object, must satisfy two logical conditions. The premises must include
|
||
> at least one universal law, whose inclusion is essential to the
|
||
> deduction of the explicandum. And the premises must also contain a
|
||
> suitable number of initial conditions." (page 32)
|
||
|
||
In the case of the explanation of scientific laws, however:
|
||
|
||
> "...all the premises are universal statements; (and) there is more than
|
||
> one premise, each of which is essential in the derivation of the
|
||
> exp1icandum..." (page 34)
|
||
|
||
> "...at least one of the premises must be 'more general' than the law
|
||
> being explained." (page 37)
|
||
|
||
The notion of 'more general' is discussed at length, and is defined as
|
||
follows:
|
||
|
||
> "Let L~1~ be a law (or a set of laws and theories constituting some
|
||
> science such as physics), and let 'P~1~' 'P~2~' . . . , 'P~n~' be a set
|
||
> of 'primitive' predicates in terms of which the predicates occuring in
|
||
> L~1~ are in some sense definable. (For the sake of simplicity, and
|
||
> without any loss of the generality of statement, we shall assume that
|
||
> the predicates are all adjectives or 'one-place' predicates such as
|
||
> 'rigid' or 'heavy' .... ) Similarly, let 'Q~1~' 'Q~2~' . . . , 'Q~n~' be
|
||
> the corresponding set of primitives for a law L~2~. Finally, let K be a
|
||
> class of objects, each of which can be significantly (or meaningfully)
|
||
> characterised, whether truly or falsely, by the predicates of either set
|
||
> .... We shall also say that an object in K satisfies a law L
|
||
> 'non-vacuously' only if the object actually possesses the various traits
|
||
> mentioned in the law and, moreover, the traits do stand to each other in
|
||
> the relations asserted by the law...
|
||
>
|
||
> We now assume the following conditions: (1) Some (and perhaps all) of
|
||
> the predicates in the first set occur in the second, but some predicates
|
||
> in the second set do not occur in the first set. (2) Every object in K
|
||
> has at least one P-property, that is, a property designated by a
|
||
> predicate in the first set. (3) There is a non-empty subclass A of
|
||
> objects in K possessing only P-properties. (4) There is a non-empty
|
||
> subclass ~~A~~ of objects in K each of which possesses at least one Q-
|
||
> property that is not a P-property. .... (5) There is a non-empty (but
|
||
> not necessarily proper) subclass B of objects in K each of which
|
||
> satisfies L~1~ non-vacuously, and such that some objects in B belong to
|
||
> A while others belong to ~~A~~. .... (6) There is a non-empty subclass C
|
||
> of objects in A for which L~2~ holds non-vacuously, and such that some
|
||
> (and perhaps all) of the objects in C also belong to B ..... When these
|
||
> six conditions are fulfilled, L~1~ may be said to be more general in K
|
||
> than L~2~." (pp 40- 41).
|
||
|
||
(my transcription differs from the original in. that where Nagel uses a
|
||
character formed of an upper case letter A with a bar over it, I have
|
||
used a struck-through A; and, more significantly, Nagel uses an unbarred
|
||
A in condition 4. From my understanding of the text I have assumed this
|
||
is a misprint, and have substituted an struck-through A.)
|
||
**TODO** check typography as processed by Markdown!
|
||
|
||
Deductive explanations, as stated above, have the general form of the
|
||
syllogism Barbara. However, Nagel adds a condition: while all the
|
||
clauses of Barbara are universally quantified, one of the premisses must
|
||
be more general than the conclusion to qualify as an explanation of it.
|
||
In the case of an explanation about a singularity, it is trivial that
|
||
the 'universal law' is more general than the 'initial conditions'; in
|
||
the case of explanations of generalities, Nagel has gone to lengths to
|
||
assert this condition.
|
||
|
||
Nagel rejects as too strong the Aristotelian requirements that the
|
||
premises of a deductive explanation should not only be true but should
|
||
be *known* to be true, and that they should be ‘better known' than the
|
||
explicandum. He observes that the 'universal premises' which are
|
||
subsumed into 'scientific laws' are true. Instead he suplies the weaker
|
||
condition that:
|
||
|
||
> "...the explanatory premises be compatible with established empirical
|
||
> facts and be in addition 'adequately supported' (or 'made probable') by
|
||
> evidence based on data other than the observational data upon which the
|
||
> acceptance of the explicandum is based." (p 43)
|
||
|
||
> "In maintaining that the premises in an explanation must be 'better
|
||
> known' than the explicandum, Aristotle was thus simply making explicit
|
||
> his conception of science. This conception is true of nothing that can
|
||
> be identified as part of the asserted content of modern empirical
|
||
> science," (p 45)
|
||
|
||
#### Probabilistic explanations
|
||
|
||
Nagel's second category, probabilistic explanations, depend not on
|
||
formal implication of the explicandum by the premises contained within the
|
||
explanation, but on some 'statistical reregularity' taking the general form:
|
||
|
||
Most x are y
|
||
a is x
|
||
=> it is probable that a is y
|
||
|
||
Nagel notes that:
|
||
|
||
> "It is still an unsettled question whether an explanation must contain a
|
||
> statistical assumption in order to be a probabilistic one, or whether
|
||
> nonstatistical premises may make an explicandum 'probable' in some
|
||
> nonstatistical sense of the word." (p 23)
|
||
|
||
Such explanations can be expressed in the Toulmin scheme (see below);
|
||
but as syllogisms have the general form IAA, which is not valid.
|
||
|
||
These two types are the models of scientific explanation that Nagel
|
||
describes; but he also describes two other categories. These are
|
||
explanation types which appear in natural conversation, and in law and
|
||
the humanities.
|
||
|
||
#### Functional (teleological) explanations
|
||
|
||
Functional (teleological) explanations are explanations which refer to
|
||
the supposed purpose of the explicandum:
|
||
|
||
> "lt is characteristic of functional explanations that they employ such
|
||
> typical locutions as 'in order that', 'for the sake of' and the like." (p 24)
|
||
|
||
There are two sub classes of functional explanation. One is the
|
||
explanation of a particular instance or occurrence: .. .
|
||
|
||
'I caught hold of the branch so that I would not fall.'
|
||
|
||
whereas the other explains something which occurs in all instances of a
|
||
particular class:
|
||
|
||
'Birds have wings so that they can fly.'
|
||
|
||
#### Genetic explanations
|
||
|
||
Genetic explanations seek to explain why something is the way it is by
|
||
explaining how it came to be this way:
|
||
|
||
'My arm is broken because I fell out of a tree'
|
||
|
||
'Penguins have wings because they evolved from birds which could fly'
|
||
|
||
It is clear that these are categories where the explanations are neither
|
||
necessary nor sufficient causes of the explicanda; you don't have to
|
||
fall out of a tree to break your arm, and you can break it without
|
||
falling out. Likewise, there may have been other ways of not falling
|
||
than catching hold of a branch, and catching hold of a branch may not
|
||
prevent a fall.
|
||
|
||
But there are statistical probabilities (not necessarily high) that
|
||
catching the branch will prevent the fall, and that a fall will lead to
|
||
a broken arm.
|
||
|
||
> "It is therefore a reasonable conclusion that genetic explanations are
|
||
> by and large probabilistic." (p 26)
|
||
|
||
### The radical critics
|
||
|
||
These conventional arguments in the philosophy of science were
|
||
dramatically disturbed in the 1960s by radical philosophers like Thomas
|
||
Kuhn [Kuhn, 62] and Paul Feyerabend [Feyerabend, 78; and passim].
|
||
Their attack was not directed specifically at accounts of explanation,
|
||
but at the empiricist and realist views of science as such - which is to
|
||
say the view – implicit in both – that we can directly access the
|
||
external world in order to gain knowledge which would support a theory.
|
||
|
||
The damage to the account of explanation was almost incidental in this
|
||
process. It was fatal, however; the consensual view of explanation did
|
||
not survive. A number of accounts of explanation have developed since
|
||
then; dissapointingly, these all seem to be timid and conservative,
|
||
attempting to preserve a view of science which is no longer tenable.
|
||
Following (but not, as far as I am aware, prior to) the radicals
|
||
onslaught, writers on the philosophy of science developed a formidable
|
||
arsenal of objections to the deductive-nomological account. I cite here
|
||
a few drawn from [Korner 75]:
|
||
|
||
Achinstein, in his note The Object of Explanation, gives some 'standard
|
||
counler-examp|es':
|
||
|
||
> "1\. We see a fire engine which is black and demand an explanation. Here
|
||
> is one that satisfies the D-N model:
|
||
>
|
||
>> This fire engine is the same colour as that crow.
|
||
|
||
>> All crows are black.
|
||
|
||
>> =>This fire engine is black.
|
||
>
|
||
> 2\. A bridge collapses and we demand an explanation. Here is one that
|
||
> satisfies the D-N model:
|
||
>
|
||
>> An engineer with years of training and experience examined the bridge
|
||
>> and said it would collapse.
|
||
|
||
>> Whenever an engineer with years of training and experience examines a
|
||
>> bridge and says it will collapse, it does.
|
||
|
||
>> => The bridge collapsed.
|
||
>
|
||
> These are unacceptable as explanations .... " (page 35)
|
||
|
||
Hesse, in her rejoinder to Achinstein, writes:
|
||
|
||
> “... there are by now at least three widely accepted general
|
||
consequences of the ensuing debate which are enough to show that this
|
||
model is by no means to be taken as the 'standard model of explanation'.
|
||
|
||
> These are:
|
||
|
||
> (i) It has grave shortcomings as an explication of the structure of
|
||
> explanation in natural science itself.
|
||
|
||
> (ii) The question of whether it usefully applies to explanation in
|
||
> history, psychology, and the social sciences is a matter of current
|
||
> controversy.
|
||
|
||
> (iii) The question of whether *any* model applying to the natural
|
||
> sciences is adequate also for these human sciences is also highly
|
||
> controversial." (page 46, Hesse's emphasis)
|
||
|
||
and finally, Salmon, in a piece entitled Theoretical Explanation,
|
||
argues:
|
||
|
||
> "... contra Hempel and many others - that an explanation \[of a
|
||
particular event\] is not 'an argument to the effect that the event to
|
||
be explained was to be expected by reason of certain explanatory
|
||
facts'...
|
||
|
||
> In addition, I have claimed that the so-called deductive- nomological
|
||
model of explanation of particular events is incorrect. It is not merely
|
||
that there are explanandum events which seem explainable only
|
||
inductively or statistically... There are also cases – such as the man
|
||
who takes his wife's birth control pills and avoids pregnancy – in which
|
||
an obviously defective explanation fulfills the conditions for
|
||
deductive-nomological explanation. (pp 118-119; the embedded quote is
|
||
from Hempel, Explanation in Science and in History, in Colodny, ed,
|
||
Frontiers of Science and Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh Press,
|
||
Pittsburgh, 1962. The italics are Salmon's. This birth control example
|
||
is also mentioned in for example van Frassen 1980)
|
||
|
||
[Here insert some detailed analysis of Feyerabend's position, and
|
||
passing reference to Lakatos and Kuhn]
|
||
|
||
### van Fraassen
|
||
|
||
Another philosopher who has attracted attention with his work on
|
||
explanation in recent years is Bas van Fraassen. His work seems directed,
|
||
however, not primarily at providing better accounts of explanation, so
|
||
much as at defending the empirical view of science from the realist critics of
|
||
it - surely, at this late date, a redundant activity. The work is marred, in my
|
||
opinion, by intellectually dishonest treatment of the radicals, to whom van Fraassen
|
||
has no honest response.
|
||
|
||
#### van Fraassen's response to the radicals
|
||
|
||
van Fraassen published his ‘the Scientific Image' in 1980, in the age of
|
||
Feyerabend and Kuhn. He mentions both these authors twice, and is
|
||
clearly familiar with their theses, describing Feyerabend's work as 'well known'
|
||
(page 14), and paraphrasing one of Feyerabend's central points (although
|
||
without acknowledging it):
|
||
|
||
> "... one theory says that there are electrons, and the other says that
|
||
there may not be. Even if the observable phenomena are as Rutherford
|
||
says, the unobservable may be different. However, the positivists
|
||
would say, if you argue that way, you automatically become a prey to
|
||
scepticism. You will have to admit that there are possibilities that you
|
||
cannot prove or disprove by experiment, and so you will have to say we
|
||
cannot know what the world is like. Worse; you will have no reason to
|
||
reject any number of outlandish possibilities; demons, witchcraft,
|
||
hidden powers contirbuting to fantastic ends." (page 35, my emphasis)
|
||
|
||
Well yes, precisely. And although it is possible that the positivists
|
||
would say it, Feyerabend did say it, repeatedly; and the choice of words seems to
|
||
me to betray a consciousness of this \[see for example Feyerabend, 81, vol 1,
|
||
foot of page 196 - which other evidence (below) shows us van Fraassen was
|
||
familiar with\]. But the only time van Fraassen addresses an argument of
|
||
Feyerabend's directly, he dismisses it as '...a totally false issue...' (page 93).
|
||
Let us look a little at the context for this.
|
||
|
||
van Fraassen is discussing the centrality of explanation to science,
|
||
citing - and accepting - Nagel's strong claim \[Nagel 61, page 4\], and using
|
||
incidentally the same passage from Nagel as Feyerabend had used in his earlier
|
||
critique of this work \[Feyerabend 81, page 52; this paper originally published in BJPS
|
||
vol 16, 1964\] to illustrate this. He claims that Nagel's view does not entail
|
||
realism, but will equally support an empiricist view. He now claims that Feyerabend
|
||
has advanced the '..totally false..' argument that, in his paraphrase:
|
||
|
||
> '...only Realism is a philosophy that stimulates scientific enquiry; anti-realism hampers it." \[page 93\]
|
||
|
||
This is a position that Feyerabend advanced? Really? Feyerabend whose
|
||
central thesis might be summed up in his phrase "The only principle that
|
||
does not inhibit progress is: anything goes." \[Feyerabend 75, p10: F's
|
||
emphasis\]. van Fraassen refers us to Feyerabend's paper \[in Feyerabend 81 vol 1\]. What Feyerabend in fact says (forgive me if I
|
||
quote at length) is:
|
||
|
||
> "To sum up: the issue between realism and instrumentalism has
|
||
A many facets..... There are arguments for instrumentalism which
|
||
concern specific theories such as the quantum theory or the
|
||
heliocentric hypothesis and which are based on specific facts and well
|
||
confirmed theories. It was shown that to demand realism in these cases
|
||
amounts to demanding support for implausible conjectures which
|
||
possess no independent empirical support and which are inconsistent
|
||
with facts and well confirmed theories. It was also shown that this is a
|
||
plausible demand which immediately follows from the principle of
|
||
testability. Hence realism is preferable to instrumentalism even in
|
||
these most difficult cases." \[Feyerabend 81 vol 1 pp 201-2; Feyerabend's emphasis.\]
|
||
|
||
'Realism is preferable to instrumentalism'. That is a very different
|
||
(and far weaker) claim than 'only Realism stimulates scientific enquiry'. So the
|
||
totally false issue is of van Fraassen's own devising, and has nothing
|
||
to do with Feyerabend.
|
||
|
||
I have gone on at some length about van Fraassen's slight (and
|
||
slighting) mention of Feyerabend. Why? Well, because van Fraassen, continuing the
|
||
now moribund debate between realism and empiricism in order to defend the
|
||
latter, addresses Feyerabend's criticisms of neither doctrine. This seems an
|
||
extraordinary ommission.
|
||
|
||
<Here insert some stuff about van Fs account of explanation...>
|
||
|
||
### Achinstein
|
||
|
||
One of the first attempts to recover an account of explanation from this
|
||
mess is that of Achinstein \[Achinstein 83\]. Achinstein distinguishes
|
||
between the act of explaining, which is an utterance, and the
|
||
explanation, which is the product of the act. This act must take place
|
||
in an appropriate context.
|
||
|
||
His project is to answer three questions: .
|
||
|
||
1. What is an explaining act?
|
||
2. What is the product of an explaining act?
|
||
3. How should explanations be evaluated?
|
||
|
||
#### 'Explaining acts'
|
||
|
||
Achinstein claims that 'explaining acts' have a period, and a completion
|
||
point.
|
||
|
||
'John was explaining why x'
|
||
|
||
'John explained x'
|
||
|
||
The latter form implies a completion has occurred.
|
||
|
||
An explanation has not occurred until the act of explanation has
|
||
occurred. For John to have explained why x, it is not sufficient that he
|
||
knew why x.
|
||
|
||
'Explaining' is illocutionary \[see Austin, how to do things with
|
||
words\]; it is done in an appropriate context. Out of such a context,
|
||
the same statement would be an equivalent perlocutary act:
|
||
'enlightening', 'getting <the auditor> to understand'.
|
||
|
||
The intention of an explaining act must be to engender understanding of
|
||
the explicanda. Achinstein does not state, but may be taken to imply,
|
||
that for such an act to take place there must (at any rate in the mind
|
||
of the explainer) be some explainee or auditor, in whose mind
|
||
understanding is to be engendered[Achinstein 1].
|
||
|
||
> "The first condition expresses what I take to be a fundamental
|
||
relationship between explaining and understanding. It is that S explains
|
||
q by uttering u only if
|
||
|
||
> 1. S utters u with the intention that his utterance of u render q
|
||
understandable."(Page ??)
|
||
|
||
Under this account it is impossible to explain something by accident – a
|
||
rather over strict condition, l think.
|
||
|
||
Achinstein also claims that it is neccesary that the utterance produced
|
||
by the explaining act must be (at least believed to be) a correct
|
||
account:
|
||
|
||
> "2. S believes that u expresses a proposition that is a correct answer
|
||
to Q...
|
||
|
||
Often people will present hints, clues, or instructions which do not
|
||
themselves answer the questions... Some hints, no doubt, border on being
|
||
answers to the question. But in those cases where they do not, it is not
|
||
completely appropriate to speak of explaining."(p 17)
|
||
|
||
Thus explanation by analogy is no explanation; again, this seems a very
|
||
strong condition. Yet Achinstein goes on to make this even stronger by
|
||
the assertion that the proposition expressed by u is itself a complete
|
||
answer to Q:
|
||
|
||
> "3. S utters u with the intention that his utterance render q
|
||
understandable by producing the knowledge, of the proposition expressed
|
||
by u, that it is a correct answer to Q."(p 18)
|
||
|
||
Atchinstein goes on to say that 'explain' can be used in two senses: a
|
||
loose sense, in which any situation fulfilling the above contains an
|
||
explanation; and a more restricted sense, which will "cover only correct
|
||
explainings". He does not describe how these may be differentiated,
|
||
however.
|
||
|
||
#### Understanding
|
||
|
||
If explaining is to be seen as an act directed at engendering
|
||
understanding, some account of what is meant by 'understanding' must be
|
||
supplied. Achinstein asserts that:
|
||
|
||
"One understands q only if one knows a correct answer to Q which one
|
||
knows to be correct (sic)... we can say that a necessary condition for
|
||
the truth of sentences of the form 'At understands q' is
|
||
|
||
> "(∀x)(A knows of x that it is a correct answer to Q)" (p 23 - 4)
|
||
|
||
Achinstein's essential problem is quite simple to express: he wants to
|
||
say that one doesn't understand something until one not only knows a
|
||
proposition which expresses the reason for it, and knows that this
|
||
proposition does in fact express the 'correct' reason, but also has
|
||
internalised this proposition.
|
||
|
||
#### 'Content-giving Propositions'
|
||
|
||
Achinstein identifies a class of nouns which he describes as
|
||
'content-giving', such as 'explanation', 'meaning', 'fact', 'reason'. He
|
||
then defines a class of propositions, constructed using such nouns and
|
||
the verb to be, which he calls 'content-giving propositions'. These take
|
||
roughly the form:
|
||
|
||
'the <cg-noun> {that | of | for} <proposition x> is
|
||
<proposition y>'
|
||
|
||
Achinstein now expands his definition of understanding to:
|
||
|
||
> "(∃p)(A knows of p that it is a correct answer to Q, and p is a complete
|
||
content-giving proposition with respect to Q)" (p 42) .
|
||
|
||
Achinstein examines a number or accounts of the epistemic nature of an
|
||
explanation, largely to use them as Aunt Sallies, before presenting his
|
||
preferred account. He examines first explanation considered as sentence
|
||
and as proposition.
|
||
|
||
These are rejected for reasons which appear to me quite strange.
|
||
Achinstein has trouble with the idea that two sentences can be
|
||
differently constructed but have the same meaning. E.g.:
|
||
|
||
>"...since sentence (1) ≠ sentence (2), the explanation of Bill's stomach
|
||
ache given by Dr. Smith ≠ the explanation of Bill's stomach ache given
|
||
by Dr. Robinson, which seems unsatisfactory. Intuitively, both doctors
|
||
have given the same explanation..."(p 76)
|
||
|
||
What Achinstein dearly wants is some Leibnitzian language in which he
|
||
can express the semantic content of the sentences. Not having one, it is
|
||
not sufficient for him to posit that such a thing must exist; so he
|
||
claims that behind every sentence there is a (presumably unique)
|
||
proposition, in English. Thus:
|
||
|
||
> "Since sentences (1) and (2) express the same proposition we can
|
||
conclude that the explanations given by the doctors are the same."(p 76)
|
||
|
||
For evidence that the proposition is considered to be unique, see the
|
||
bizarre argument presented as the ’Locutionary Force Problem' on p 77.
|
||
ln this (by my reading) he claims that:
|
||
|
||
ix if the product of an explanation is a proposition, and it is possible
|
||
to produce, as separate acts of explanation and of criticism, utterances
|
||
which map onto the same proposition, then that proposition is at once a
|
||
criticism and an explanation, which is absurd. Therefore the product of
|
||
an explanation cannot be a proposition.
|
||
|
||
I doubt whether this argument has meaning, let alone force. ln this and
|
||
other arguments, Achinstein seems to confound operations which would be
|
||
legitimate on some formal grammar with what it is possible to do with
|
||
natural language.
|
||
|
||
His view that propositions are unique is made more difficult to maintain
|
||
by his apparent identification of the propositions themselves with the
|
||
sequence of symbols used to represent it. For a statement of the view
|
||
that sequences of symbols are efficient (i.e. that they may have many
|
||
differing meanings), see e.g. \[Barwise and Perry 86, p S2\]; ,
|
||
|
||
He also has trouble with emphasis shifts in propositions which are
|
||
represented by the same sequence of word-tokens, which he resolves by
|
||
the concept of 'e-sentences' - sentences with additional flagging to
|
||
indicate the central phrase, so that:
|
||
|
||
> "(7) the e-sentence 'Bill ate *spoiled meat* on Tuesday' is not identical with
|
||
> (8) the e-sentence 'Bill ate spoiled meat *on Tuesday*"' (p 80)
|
||
|
||
He next considers the deductive-nomological view - the view that an explanation is an argument.
|
||
|
||
Achinstein argues that the form of the deductive nomological explanation
|
||
can be seen as an ordered pair <conjunction of premises, conclusion>.
|
||
This view is dismissed for reasons analogous to those above.
|
||
|
||
#### Explanation as ordered pair
|
||
|
||
Having considered, and dismissed, the preceding accounts of explanation,
|
||
Achinstein now proposes that explanation should be considered to be an ordered
|
||
pair <x, y>
|
||
|
||
s.t.:
|
||
|
||
> "The explanation of q given by S denotes (x; y) if and only if
|
||
>
|
||
> (i) Q is a content-question;
|
||
> (ii) x is a complete content-giving proposition with respect to Q;
|
||
> (iii) y = explaining q;
|
||
> (iv) (£a)(£u)\[a is an act in which S explained q by uttering u -> (r)(r is associated with with a;r=x)\]. (i.e., x is the one and only A proposition associated with every act in which S explained q by \`uttering something.)"(p 87)
|
||
|
||
What this appears to boil down to is this:
|
||
|
||
Achinstein believes any given concatenation of symbols representing a proposition to be identical with that proposition; and that any
|
||
proposition is unique.
|
||
|
||
Thus each and every occurance of this sequence of symbols is the same
|
||
thing.
|
||
|
||
Yet he believes, as shown above, that it is impossible for (e.g.) an
|
||
explanation to
|
||
|
||
In fact, Achinstein's claim is even stronger than this, for he believes
|
||
that there is some proposition 'underneath' each sentence; thus, potentially, many
|
||
sentences may map onto the same proposition, and consequently all these sentences may be
|
||
treated as being identical (l).
|
||
|
||
be 'the same thing' as (e.g.) a criticism. So it is impossible for an
|
||
explanation to be identical with an occurance of a sequence of symbols.
|
||
|
||
Thus an ordered pair must be constructed, in which the symbol-sequence
|
||
is linked with another symbol sequence which represents a reference to the
|
||
question which was asked.
|
||
|
||
Note that q, the question, is also a sequence of symbols; so that a
|
||
pair:
|
||
|
||
<\[all plants are green\]; \[answering: "why is this grass
|
||
green"\]> .
|
||
|
||
is unique, and is always the same explanation. Therefore (since
|
||
Achinstein's schema makes no mention of an auditor) it is always either a good
|
||
explanation or always a bad one, regardless of whether the question was asked by a three year
|
||
old child or a plant physiologist.
|
||
|
||
I would like to return the readers attention to Achinstein's claim that:
|
||
|
||
> "One understands q only if one knows a correct answer to Q which one knows to be correct " \[p 23, my emphasis\]
|
||
|
||
and goes on to clarify that, by this, he implies '...a de re sense of
|
||
knowing.'
|
||
|
||
The use of 'correct' here is the problem. It appears to imply that one
|
||
knows that the answer which one knows maps in some unproblematic way onto something
|
||
real in the external world. Thus Achinstein, too, falls into the trap
|
||
sprung by the radicals. In the absence of some definition of what is to be understood
|
||
by 'correct', these definitions are simply meaningless.
|
||
|
||
This account does not address many of the facets of common sense
|
||
explanation.
|
||
|
||
It has nothing to say about the amount of detail contained in an
|
||
explanation. It has nothing to say about the need to express an explanation in terms of an
|
||
account of the world which is accessible to the auditor. lt fails to account for
|
||
the possibility of explanation by analogy, or of unintentional explanation.
|
||
|
||
It appears that Achinstein's motivation in producing a new account has
|
||
less to do with addressing these real world problems than with overcoming such
|
||
philosophical puzzles as the Paradox of the Ravens; so his account takes
|
||
us no nearer to providing a model which will support the construction of
|
||
better common sense explanations.
|
||
|
||
## Toulmin
|
||
|
||
Turning aside for the moment from those philosophers who have made a
|
||
study of explanation per se, there is another whose work is currently
|
||
attracting fashionable attention in Expert Systems (and especially mechanised
|
||
explanation) circles; one must make passing reference to Toulmin, and, unless one
|
||
chooses to use his argument schema, one must produce a very good argument for not
|
||
doing so. Therfore it is important to know what he actually argued.
|
||
|
||
A Toulmin's programme was to replace the syllogistic with a new logical
|
||
schema of his own. He did not address symbolic logic except by
|
||
dismissing it as irrelevant to the study of real world arguments:
|
||
|
||
> "We shall have to replace mathematically-idealised logical
|
||
relations - timeless context-free relations between either statements
|
||
or propositions — by relations which in practical fact are no more than
|
||
the statements to which they relate. This is not to say that the
|
||
elaborate mathematical systems which constitute 'symbolic logic' must
|
||
now be thrown away; but only that people with intellectual capital
|
||
invested in them should retain no illusions about the extent of their
|
||
relevance to practical arguments." (Toulmin 58, p 185)
|
||
|
||
or again:
|
||
|
||
> "...the question needs to be pressed, whether this branch of
|
||
mathematics (propositional calculus) is entitled to the name 'logical
|
||
theory'. If we give it this name, we imply that the propositional
|
||
calculus plays a part in the assessment of actual arguments comparable
|
||
to that played by physical theory in explaining actual physical
|
||
phenomena. But this we have seen reason to doubt: this branch of
|
||
mathematics does not form the theoretical part of logic... By now, the
|
||
mathematicians logic has become a frozen calculus, having no
|
||
functional connection with the canons for assessing the strength and
|
||
cogency of arguments." (Ibid, p 186 - and he goes on in this vein!)
|
||
|
||
**TODO**: I can use precisely this - and van Frassen's work, too - to illustrate and underline my case later that the purpose of argument is hegemonistic, not truth-seeking. This is so clearly polemical.
|
||
|
||
These contentions seem polemical, even propagandistic, in tone; they are
|
||
certainly not, in Tou|min‘s own terminology, 'candid'. They advance
|
||
scant evidence in support of their allegations. They seem out of place in a
|
||
work whose matter is the analysis of argument; and they lie especially uneasy with
|
||
Touimin's claim to be seeking to make argument more scrutable.
|
||
|
||
He goes on to attack the concept of ‘logicaI form' and 'formal validity'
|
||
in argument:
|
||
|
||
> "...the suggestion that validity is to be explained in terms of
|
||
'formal properties', in any geometric sense, loses its plausibility."
|
||
(Ibid, p 120)
|
||
|
||
He argues that the conception that arguments in general could or should
|
||
have a logical form arises out of a false start in the study of logic:
|
||
|
||
> "The development of logical theory... began historically with the
|
||
study of a rather special class of arguments -\_ namely, the class of
|
||
unequivocal, analytic, formally valid arguments with a universal
|
||
statement as 'major premiss'. Arguments in this class are exceptional
|
||
in four different ways, which together make them a bad example for
|
||
general study." (Ibid, p 144)
|
||
|
||
Clearly, if arguments have no logical form, it is not possible to
|
||
advance a decision process for them, and Toulmin does not attempt to do so.
|
||
Rather, the burden of his argument is that decision processes are (for real world
|
||
arguments) impossible in principle.
|
||
|
||
Thus those practitioners in the field of Expert Systems who advance
|
||
Toulmin as an authority must face up to this corrolary: if Toulmin's
|
||
arguments are valid, then there cannot ever be a successful Expert System based on any
|
||
technology we have now available, as all current Expert Systems are based on some
|
||
logical formalism (even if, as in the case of production systems, this formalism
|
||
is crude); and all, certainly, claim to be decision processes for arguments
|
||
in their domain. As such, according to Toulmin, they are the modern equivalents
|
||
of the PhiIosophers' stone - they cannot exist.
|
||
|
||
He was, to be fair to him, writing in the year that LISP was being
|
||
developed, when the posibility of mechanical inference was dreamed of only by
|
||
visionaries like Turing; nevertheless the cavalier manner in which he dismisses all
|
||
of the 19th and 20th century advances in logic significantly weakens his claims
|
||
to be taken seriously in this field.
|
||
|
||
But if Toulmin cannot be taken seriously as a logician, is there any
|
||
residual value in his work on argument? I think it is possible that there is,
|
||
because the argument schema with which he hoped to replace both the traditional
|
||
syllogism, and the formalisms of modern logic, does indeed capture the content of
|
||
normal conversational discussion in an easily manageable form. Had Toulmin
|
||
advanced this and this only, I think he might have been taken more seriously; and
|
||
I think there is merit in the current revival of interest in it.
|
||
|
||
### The Toulmin Schema
|
||
|
||
Toulmin's concern is with arguments as they are presented informally, in
|
||
conversation or writing, and the relation between the form of such
|
||
informal arguments and the forms recognised by formal logic.
|
||
|
||
He questions whether the aristotelian 'standard form' of an argument is
|
||
'candid'; that is, whether it is presented in such a way as to make its
|
||
merits as argument most manifest. He suggests that the analysis into only three
|
||
elements, major premiss, minor premiss, conclusion may be artificially simplified:
|
||
|
||
> "Simplicity is of course a merit, but may it not in this case have
|
||
been bought too dearly? Can we properly classify all the elements in
|
||
our arguments under the three headings, 'major premiss', 'minor
|
||
premiss' and 'conclusion', or are these categories misleadingly few in
|
||
number? Is there even enough similarity between major and minor
|
||
premisses for them usefully to be yoked together by the single
|
||
name...?"
|
||
|
||
He draws on the practice of jurisprudence to find alternative schemae;
|
||
and synthesises one such comprising the following elements: a statement of
|
||
some assertion, which implicitly carries with it a claim as to the
|
||
truth of the assertion; and data, information which is consensual at the time of
|
||
argument (or is supported by some futher argument), which tends to support that
|
||
claim; some inference rule, a warrant, which will allow the argument to move from
|
||
the data to the claim (for example, 'all as are bs'), again optionally supported
|
||
by some further argument or bagking; an optional qualifier (e.g. 'probably', 'I
|
||
believe'); and, implicit in the qualifier, the possibility of a rebuttal:
|
||
|
||

|
||
|
||
In conversation, Toulmin argues, it may be natural simply to say
|
||
'<data> so <claim>' ; to say '<claim> because <warrant> because
|
||
<data>' "...strikes us as cumbrous and artificial, for it puts in an extra step which is trivial
|
||
and unnecessary".
|
||
|
||
Toulmin sets out to validate this schema by comparing it with the
|
||
syllogism, and asking "'What corresponds in the syllogism to our distinction
|
||
between data, warrant, and backing?"' He devotes special attention to arguments of the
|
||
forms 'Almost all A's are B's' and 'Scarcely any A's \_are B's' - forms which
|
||
are, of course, of the utmost importance in default logics, but which are beyond
|
||
the scope of the syllogistic. He shows that such arguments are representable
|
||
using his schema without difficulty, and that the traditional syllogism forms
|
||
are also so representable.
|
||
|
||
But beyond this he observes that the major premiss of a syllogism
|
||
plays a dual role with hegemonistic implications: it is at once an inference
|
||
step and an assertion of some piece of information. Thus one may challenge it in its
|
||
role as warrant, on the basis that it is not relevant to the case, and as
|
||
backing, on the grounds that it is not true. TouImin's schema, by separating these
|
||
roles, makes clearer from what grounds a counter argument can be launched.
|
||
|
||
{**TODO**: Again back-reference this when I'm arguing that argument is hegemonistic!}
|
||
|
||
While TouImin's ambitious claims for his schema as the authoritative
|
||
representation of argument - and his audacious dismissal of modern logic
|
||
- seem unworthy of attention, his representation schema does offer some merits
|
||
in the representation of real world arguments, especially those which appeal to
|
||
default reasoning. Furthermore, the fact that these argument structures can be
|
||
'daisy-chained' offers a convenient way to pack up large arguments into a
|
||
structure which can be unfolded to any given level of detail, and this property
|
||
makes the schema an interesting candidate argument representation as we look for
|
||
ways to control the amount of detail revealed to the user of an Expert System.
|
||
|
||
His contention that argument can be hegemonic is one which I shall want
|
||
to examine further.
|
||
|
||
## Towards a Situation Semantic account of Explanation
|
||
|
||
Part of Barwise and Perry's programme in constructing Situation
|
||
Semantics was to elucidate the problem of the transfer of knowledge from one
|
||
person to another, and this is, of course, one of the central problems in an
|
||
account of explanation.
|
||
|
||
However, they give no account of explanation as such. What follows is my
|
||
guess at what their account would look like, had they formally stated
|
||
it. This should not be taken too seriously, as their formalism is rich and
|
||
complex, and I have by no means mastered it. Certainly, any howlers in what follows all
|
||
my own work.
|
||
|
||
My first ‘cut’ at the problem looked like this. An explanation was to be
|
||
that which happened in a situation E defined:
|
||
|
||
E := at I1: understands, a, c; no
|
||
understands, b, c; yes
|
||
enquirlng, a; yes
|
||
addressing, a, b; yes
|
||
saying, a, q; yes
|
||
subject, q, c; yes
|
||
|
||
at I2: responding, b, q; yes
|
||
addressing, b, a; yes
|
||
saying, b, u; yes
|
||
subject, u, c; yes
|
||
|
||
at I3: understands, a, c; yes
|
||
understands, b, c; yes
|
||
|
||
I1 < I2 < I3
|
||
|
||
where: a, b are some actors; c is some concept; q, u are some
|
||
utterances.
|
||
|
||
This begs a number of questions. Firstly, what relationship is meant by
|
||
’understands, x, y' ? This question is, of course, the central one for
|
||
the whole programme of Situation Semantics; when it can be answered, the programme
|
||
will have succeeded. Secondly, how can we represent the (presumed)
|
||
causal dependence of the understanding at I3 on the responding at I2 ? Thirdly,
|
||
what implications (if any) does this have for the semantic content of u?
|
||
|
||
However, this definition does have some points of value. Firstly, an
|
||
explanation is located in a situation with at least two roles (which,
|
||
incidentally, cannot be taken by the same individual); secondly, a
|
||
transfer of understanding takes place. Neither of these points are met by
|
||
traditional accounts.
|
||
|
||
So what we need to add is something like this. The sage's response, u,
|
||
must be seen as a list of statements \[s1, s2, ... sn\], Such that, for any
|
||
statement sj in u, sj is understandable in terms of \[<student's state of knowledge
|
||
at I1> + s1 + Sj-1\]. and also that c, the concept originally asked about, is
|
||
understandable in terms of \[<student's state of knowledge at I1> +
|
||
sj + ... + sn\]. This (fortunately) accords with Barwise and Perry's understanding:
|
||
|
||
> "An utterance u of a sentence φ gives us not just one discourse
|
||
situation d for φ that is part of u, but also discourse situations dα
|
||
for every constituent expression α of φ, discourse situations that are
|
||
also parts of u... Thus, part of what the utterance gives us is the set
|
||
>
|
||
> {dα : α is φ or a constituent of φ}
|
||
>
|
||
> of discourse situations." \[Ibid p 123\]
|
||
|
||
This is inadequate, because (among other things) it fails to represent
|
||
the negotiation which is inherent in the construction of many real world
|
||
explanations.
|
||
|
||
However, it appears to be a step along a potentially interesting path,
|
||
and one which I intend to pursue.
|
||
|
||
## A lemma concerning the nature of perception
|
||
|
||
The major argument which I wish to develop in this chapter is based on a
|
||
very important - and contentious - assumption: there may (or may not) be such
|
||
a thing as a real world, but it's existance is largely irrelevant, as if it does
|
||
exist, we are unable to percieve it directly. So before going on to advance this major
|
||
argument, I will attempt to support this lemma.
|
||
|
||
In van Fraassen's words, "the human organism is, from the point of view
|
||
of physics, a certain kind of measuring apparatus. As such, it has certain
|
||
inherent limitations... " \[van Fraassen 80, p 17\] Precisely: and as van
|
||
Fraassen observes, our perceptions of the world are conditioned by the nature of this
|
||
apparatus, and by these limitations, which, as he goes on to claim, "...wilI be described
|
||
in the final physics and biology." \[ibid\] But how can this be? We are to
|
||
investigate the nature of these instruments, using, as analytic tools, the instruments themselves.
|
||
|
||
Take for example the human eye. We know what the eye looks like; we've
|
||
seen many of them: with our eyes. We know their physical nature, because
|
||
biologists have dissected them, and using their eyes, have made careful diagrams of
|
||
what they have seen, which we, in turn, can examine using our eyes.
|
||
|
||
So, if our theories about the nature of the eye are right, and it does
|
||
indeed project a two dimensional image of a three dimensional world (supposing
|
||
such at exists) onto our retinas, then our theories about the nature of the
|
||
eye are right.
|
||
|
||
This argument is not as far fetched as it sounds: after all, the memory
|
||
of a computer \[assuming, for the moment, that such things exist\] is
|
||
strictly one dimensional - a vector of cells. Yet Computer-aided design software, for
|
||
example, or flight simulator software, renders an image from this one-dimensional
|
||
environment onto a two dimensional screen in such a way that we interpret it in
|
||
three dimensions.
|
||
|
||
If such transformations between a one dimensional reality and a three
|
||
dimensional appearance are possible in a machine, why not in our own optical
|
||
systems? [1]
|
||
|
||
Furthermore, our theories about the nature of world are conditioned by
|
||
the languages in which we express them. Different languages allow for the
|
||
description of different theories about reality. Again, different communities (or even
|
||
individuals) using what they believe to be the same language (say, for example,
|
||
English) may attatch sufficiently different interpretations to the same linguistic
|
||
symbols and constructs that communication fails, without either of the parties being
|
||
aware that it has failed. This point, about the incommensurability of (some)
|
||
theories has been made many times \[see eg Kuhn, Feyerabend\]; but some of the
|
||
consequences require exploration.
|
||
|
||
## An argument concerning the nature of explanation
|
||
|
||
Firstly, if we cannot access reality except through the medium of
|
||
theory, then Nagel's claim that an explanation is a mapping from a statement to
|
||
reality must fall.
|
||
|
||
It becomes clear that explanation can at best be a mapping from a
|
||
statement to a theory. ls this a good account of the nature of explanation? .
|
||
Well, let us consider what, in common sense, we think of as 'a good
|
||
explanation'. We feel we have recieved a good explanation if we 'understand' both the
|
||
explanation and the explicandum; if it 'makes sense': if, in fact, we do not
|
||
percieve it as grossly inconsistent with the body of 'belief' or 'knowledge’ which we already
|
||
hold.
|
||
|
||
For example, most modern Western people would not think that the
|
||
statement:
|
||
|
||
'the God Ra drives his chariot daily across the rainbow bridge'
|
||
|
||
was a good explanation of why the sun rises and sets; we do not believe
|
||
that there is a God Ra, nor that what we percieve as the sun is identical with
|
||
this being, nor that a rainbow is sufficiently rigid and strong to bear the weight of
|
||
such a being should it exist. But to a first kingdom Egyptian, it may have been an
|
||
excellent explanation. Similarly, that first kingdom Egyptian would not accept the
|
||
statement:
|
||
|
||
'the Earth rotates on its axis once every day'
|
||
|
||
as a good explanation for the occurance of the same phenomenon. He would
|
||
know perfectly well that the earth, being fixed, could not rotate on its
|
||
axis. And even if it could, why should this influence the daily ritual of Ra?
|
||
|
||
We consider an explanation good if it maps a statement about
|
||
the explicandum onto the theory, or body of belief, which we currently hold.
|
||
|
||
\[Main text of argument. In the tradition of 'philosophy of science' I
|
||
intend to draw on examples from two genuine debates, drawn in this instance from
|
||
the development of the theory of evolution. These debates are
|
||
|
||
> The debate between [Huxley and Kropotkin](HuxleyKropotkin.html) over whether co-operation or
|
||
competition was the more important factor in the survival of species.
|
||
|
||
> > Kropotkin, a leading Anarchist, sought to show that human beings (among
|
||
other animals) were inherently co-operative, and (implied conclusion)
|
||
would get along fine in the absence of government. Huxley, a Tory,
|
||
sought to show that, on the contrary, competition (and, implicitly, capitalism)
|
||
red in tooth and claw was 'natural'.
|
||
|
||
> The debate between [Bateson and Kammerer](BatesonKammerer.html) over whether acquired
|
||
characteristics were inherited.
|
||
|
||
> > Kammerer, then the only scientist capable of breeding many species of
|
||
amphibian in captivity, showed in a series of experiments that
|
||
characteristics aquired by parents were inherited by their offspring.
|
||
Bateson, in a series of increasingly virulent attacks, ultimately
|
||
claimed that these experiments were fraudulent. As no one else was even capable of
|
||
breeding the creatures involved, the experiments could not be repeated.
|
||
|
||
> > Kammerer was a communist, and the implicit argument behind his work
|
||
was that human beings were perfectable; that some parts of the benefits
|
||
of humane education and culture would be transmitted. Bateson was again a
|
||
Tory, though not as politically committed as the other figures discussed.
|
||
|
||
In these debates it is clear that the protagonists sought ot explain a
|
||
phenomenon - in this case evolution - in terms of theories which
|
||
supported their own views of the world. The act of explanation was clearly being used
|
||
as a polemic act, to try to pursuade the explainee of the correctness of the
|
||
explainers ideological stance\]
|
||
|
||
## Acknowledgments
|
||
|
||
I am grateful to Vernon Pratt for helping me clarify the consequences
|
||
that this doctrine has for the concepts of 'theory' and 'belief'. lf it is the case that
|
||
there is no access to a 'real world', then all statements about the nature of the world are of
|
||
equal - undifferentiable - validity (except in so far as some aesthetic criteria
|
||
may be applied to them). It remains possible to differentiate between a belief - an
|
||
unsupported statement about the nature of the world - and a theory: a statement that the world
|
||
has some property as a consequence of certain other properties which it may have.
|
||
However, it seems to me that this distinction is of little practical importance.
|
||
|
||
\[**TODO**: Talk about what constitutes a good explanation. Draw on work from
|
||
|
||
* Linguistics
|
||
* Psychology\]
|
||
|
||
## Referenses:
|
||
|
||
### Philosophy
|
||
|
||
Barwise & Perry, Situations and Attitudes {have this}
|
||
|
||
Feyerapend, Against Method {have this}
|
||
|
||
ven Fresssen, B Q: The Scientific Image: Clarenden Press, Oxford, 1980
|
||
|
||
Garfinkel, Forms of Explanation
|
||
|
||
Nagel, The Structure of Science
|
||
|
||
Pepper, K Conjectures and Refutations {don't have this but might be worth buying}
|
||
|
||
A Toulmin, The uses of Argument
|
||
|
||
### Linguistics
|
||
|
||
Sperber, Relevance {have this}
|
||
|
||
### Psychology
|
||
|
||
Antaki, C., (1989) ''Lay explanations of behaviour: two psychological cultures'', in *Expert Knowledge and Explanation: The Knowledge-language Interface*, Ellis, C. (ed), Ellis Harwood, London, pp 42-60.
|
||
|
||
Antaki, C: Analysing Everyday Explanation
|
||
|
||
Craik, The Nature of Explanation
|
||
|
||
Draper, S W: A User Centred Concept of Explanation: Alvey Exp SIG 2
|
||
|
||
O'Melley, Q: Applying Studies of Natural Dialogue to Human Computer Interaction: Alvey Exp SIG 2
|
||
|
||
### Artificial Intelligence
|
||
|
||
A Goguen, Reasoning and Natural Explanation \`
|
||
|
||
----
|
||
[Achinstein 1]: Later (p 19), Achinstein refers to 'the audience'. By contrast, he dcites (p 20) an alternative formulation by RJ Mattews in which the audience is explicitly represented.
|
||
[1][OnHylasAndPhilonus.html] Statement of this argument from Berkley's 'Three Dialogues of Hylas and Philonous'
|